Discussion about this post

User's avatar
Peter Gerdes's avatar

Regarding "P but I don't believe P" maybe it's relevant to consider some more complex examples"

To me it seems equally weird to say "P and Q but I don't believe P" or "P or (P and Q) but I don't believe P". However, if we increase the complexity of the left side enough it not longer seems weird, eg "The Riemann zeta hypothesis implies P but I don't believe P" seems fine even if it turns out that the Riemann zeta hypothesis is a logical truth (yes I know some ppl think mathematical truths aren't logical but, if necessary, we can make the sentence say if zeta is provable in ZFC then P).

I feel like this suggests there is at least an element of consideration of the complexity of the inference involved (and I think the same trick works on the belief side eg I don't believe P or Q is still weird).

Expand full comment
Peter Gerdes's avatar

(looks like first time substack ate this) Regarding the last puzzle does it raise a problem for your solution that "it's raining but there is only a 90% chance that's true" also seems weird?

My analysis in this is that the problem comes from the implied tension. To my ear it seems fine to assert, "It's raining and I'm only 90% sure." I think the difference is that we make the background assumption that there is some implied level of certainty required to make assertions in this context so if you don't think it reached that level why did you assert it and if you do why did you imply a tension.

I'd like to extend this to the certainty case by suggesting that saying "I'm not certain" in this context has the Gricean implicature that there is enough reason to doubt that you should take notice. But if that's so then asserting the claim in the first place violated the norm of helpfulness (if you knew I needed to know with probability at least 99% that it was raining why would you say it's raining when you only have probability 90%).

Expand full comment
13 more comments...

No posts