Discussion about this post

User's avatar
Anlam Kuyusu's avatar

My interpretation of the arbitrariness was that you could sort of whimsically pick which beliefs you want to be the foundational beliefs - or perhaps less strongly, there could be multiple, inconsistent sets of foundational beliefs.

Expand full comment
DavesNotHere's avatar

Very interesting. Does it mean I should stop citing the münchhausen trilemma?

This shows that there is more to argument than logic. Logic alone can only evaluate premises if they (or their negations) lead to a contradiction. If a premise is not a theorem of logic (or a negation of one), logic can’t say whether it is true or false, only that if it is true, it entails a conclusion.

I'm having trouble thinking of foundational beliefs, though. Lacking imagination, I guess. Maybe the example of utilitarianism's basic evaluation should satisfy me? Utilitarians could consider that to be foundational. But is it because they have this sort of justification in mind, or because they have inferred it from their experiences and various consequentialist arguments? Does it make sense to think of it as foundational if belief required seeing arguments? Can the reasons for belief be different from the reasons for considering it foundational? Or am I recapitulating the fallacy the article tries to clear up, where the reason for believing something is just some evidence, and the reason for thinking of it as foundational is because there is direct evidence for it? I should re-read later. I am probably confused.

I guess the laws of thought are foundational? But they are sort of circular, because we define propositions as statements that conform to those axioms, but the axioms also take propositions as primitive. I’m thinking of the analysis of the Liar's Paradox in Paradox Lost.

Expand full comment
5 more comments...

No posts